Saturday, October 31, 2015

HAPPY HALLOWEEN!

The following information is used for educational purposes only.




HAPPY HALLOWEEN!

























































































































































Source: Google Images

Thursday, October 29, 2015

INTPOL/GralInt-La glorificación de la muerte

The following information is used for educational purposes only.





La glorificación de la muerte

Marcos Aguinis


28 DE OCTUBRE DE 2015




Indigna la parálisis mundial frente a la glorificación de asesinatos. Con la excusa de que luchan por una justa causa y del respaldo de algunos párrafos del Corán, no se ponen en marcha acciones que desmonten esta perversión. Detrás de cada "mártir" existe una educación tenaz y alienante para que especialmente los jóvenes se arrojen a matar la mayor cantidad de personas, sean ancianos, mujeres o niños.

El Corán tiene muchas contradicciones, que se podrían interpretar como el resultado de haber sido dictado por el Profeta en diversas circunstancias de su vida. También tiene contradicciones la Biblia. Ambas obras pueden conducir al fanatismo o el diálogo, según su interpretación. Hubo guerras de religión entre los cristianos, como las hubo entre los musulmanes. Hubo y existen firmes impulsos hacia la coexistencia y la paz en las diversas denominaciones cristianas, y lo mismo podría darse en las zonas de predominio islámico.


En el Corán aparece la práctica del suicidio, pero también afirma que "nadie puede morir, sino con el permiso de Dios y según el plazo fijado" (3:145). Refuerza esta afirmación otra frase en contra del martirio: "No os matéis a vosotros mismos" (4:29).

Sobre fines del siglo XI apareció la secta de los "asesinos", término que proviene de la droga hachís o hashish (palabra árabe que dio origen a ashashín). Sus integrantes mataban a personalidades y dignatarios políticos, tanto cristianos como musulmanes. El orientalista norteamericano B. Lewis equipara los métodos y argumentos de esa secta con el actual fenómeno del terrorismo suicida. Sus practicantes usaban el cuchillo como arma porque querían perecer en la acción, convertirse en "mártires".


Debe enfatizarse, sin embargo, que pese a la importancia histórica de la yihad (guerra santa, a la que el martirio se encuentra integrado), el concepto de terrorismo suicida e indiscriminado está ausente en los textos sagrados islámicos y también en las obras de derecho y jurisprudencia musulmanes.

Pareciera que el origen del terrorismo suicida se vincula en especial a las tendencias del chiismo desarrolladas en Persia, donde el martirio tiene un papel destacado, pese a que en ese país se desarrollaron mucho el arte, la ficción y el hedonismo. Estas tendencias se vinculan con el Irán posterior a 1979, tras la reaccionaria toma del poder por los ayatollahs. Durante la guerra de Irak contra Irán, por ejemplo, Khomeini distribuyó medio millón de pequeñas llaves a centenares de miles de niños para que avanzaran de frente contra las posiciones enemigas, con la promesa de que cada llave les abriría la puerta del paraíso. Eran un escudo humano, porque tras ellos avanzaban las tropas. Hay testimonios estremecedores de soldados iraquíes que huyeron del campo de batalla ante el espectáculo de la masacre que se empezó a cometer contra esos niños. Esta práctica comenzó a extenderse en el contexto de la guerra civil libanesa de 1975-90. Y luego, en los sitios desde los cuales se lanzan misiles contra Israel, para que la respuesta produjera la muerte de esos niños-escudo, así de inmediato se denuncian como víctimas especialmente elegidas por la barbarie israelí.


Desde entonces la técnica del suicidio se tornó cada vez más frecuente. En diciembre de 1981 la embajada iraquí en Beirut fue objeto de un atentado suicida con coche bomba perpetrado por el Partido Islámico Da'wà, de tendencia proiraní. Después, en 1983, tuvieron lugar otros dos atentados suicidas con camión-bomba contra objetivos político-militares extranjeros, también protagonizados por grupos vinculados al gobierno iraní. El 18 de abril, un suicida se estrelló contra la embajada estadounidense en Beirut y causó 63 muertos y 120 heridos. Pocos meses después, el 23 de octubre, se produjo el doble atentado suicida en Beirut contra el cuartel general de los marines norteamericanos y contra el puesto de mando francés en Ramlat Al-Abida, que provocó la muerte de 241 estadounidenses y 58 franceses. En Buenos Aires fueron voladas la embajada de Israel y la sede de la AMIA mediante atentados suicidas. Gran conmoción produjo el ataque a las torres gemelas de Nueva York por aviones conducidos por "mártires".

Los primeros atentados de esta locura tanática fueron dirigidos contra objetivos políticos y militares concretos. Pero luego esto degeneró en el actual terrorismo indiscriminado, que busca el máximo número de víctimas sin importar su condición. Este terrorismo indiscriminado es fogoneado por líderes palestinos y la consciente o inconsciente complicidad de las agencias noticiosas, que no lo denuncia con claridad.

La lista de atentados cometidos contra Israel y los judíos de todo el mundo ha tenido un crecimiento análogo al del antisemitismo bajo la propaganda nazi, salvando las distancias. Antes eran la "raza inferior"; ahora, los "descendientes de cerdos y monos". En ambos casos se empieza con descalificaciones suaves que suben rápido la intensidad. Y en la última etapa se grita "barrer el Estado de Israel" y "limpiar el mundo de judíos". El Holocausto no habría sido posible si se lo hubiera denunciado y combatido a tiempo, con firmeza. Hay un perverso silencio ante las campañas que impulsan a jóvenes alienados, desocupados y sin futuro a convertirse en presuntos héroes de una causa justa.

Los presuntos "mártires" son objeto de diversos homenajes en los territorios palestinos. Allí la educación tiene mucho en común con la que se imparte en las tierras dominadas por el ISIS. El resultado es fabricar asesinos. Con lasintifadas sólo se logró demorar o paralizar las negociaciones de paz. Ahora están consiguiendo que hasta los israelíes que apoyaban a los palestinos empiecen a callar. Hoy, el presidente Mahmoud Abbas es conciliador en inglés y guerrero feroz en árabe.

Algunos opinan que es diferente la mentalidad del mundo islámico de la de Occidente. Pero no es ético frenarse ante ese discutible obstáculo. Los esfuerzos por la vida, por el progreso, por la convivencia y por la tolerancia -aunque sean descalificados por los fanáticos de cualquier tiempo y lugar- no deben conducir al silencio, la ceguera o la indiferencia. La verdad es fácil de entender -decía Galileo-, pero es difícil descubrirla. Ayudemos a descubrirla.



















Fuente: www.lanacion.com.ar

Sunday, October 18, 2015

HEALTH/GralInt-This is what happens to your brain and body when you check your phone before bed

The following information is used for educational purposes only.






This is what happens to your brain and body when you check your phone before bed


Aug. 28, 2015

Staring at screens right before sleep turns out to be a lot worse than previously thought. Dr. Dan Siegel, clinical professor of psychiatry at the UCLA School of Medicine, lays out all of the negative effects bedtime screen viewing can have on the brain and body.




















































Source:http://www.stumbleupon.com/su/1m5C3Q/:18e-Ek4ai:jq.86bxA/www.techinsider.io/impact-smartphones-brain-and-body-sleep-dan-siegel-2015-8

Saturday, October 17, 2015

¡FELIZ DÍA DE LA MADRE!

The following information is used for educational purposes only.






¡FELIZ DÍA DE LA MADRE!



AMOR INMENSO

PACIENCIA INFINITA


DEDICACION EXCLUSIVA


RESISTENCIA ABSOLUTA


ENORME CORAZÓN



...aunque no exista un manual de instrucciones de cómo ser una buena mamá, yo tuve

a la mía que podría haber escrito uno con toda su sabiduría y conocimiento que hizo

que fuera una GRAN MADRE. Gracias por haber sido mi mamá
, ciertamente LA MEJOR.




por C.M.




























































































































Fuente: Google Images

Wednesday, October 14, 2015

TECH/GralInt-Technology has hijacked family dinnertime. Watch the Pepper Hacker reclaim it.

The following information is used for educational purposes only.







Technology has hijacked family dinnertime. Watch the Pepper Hacker reclaim it.


Dolmio Australia


Published on Mar 23, 2015

Technology has hijacked family dinnertime. So to help bring families together for dinner, Dolmio created the Pepper Hacker. It cracks pepper, shuts down TVs, wipes out WiFi and


disables mobile devices. Watch our experiment reclaim family dinnertime.


Share this film and help us bring families together at dinnertime.

This is a fun experiment with the express authority of the owner of the household and participants. The technology used has not been verified or authorised for commercial

application.














































Source: www.youtube.com

Saturday, October 10, 2015

MAG/GralInt-" Reencuentros " Lucas Di Giacomo (en Suipacha, Pcia. de Buenos Aires)

The following information is used for educational purposes only.







" Reencuentros "

Lucas Di Giacomo



Published on Feb 4, 2015



“ For this project Lucas Di Giacomo went back to his home town and, along with his team, in only two weeks, rebuilt the old town´s theatre. Today, that old theatre, almost forgotten, has recovered its soul, and the people, a place to dream and play artists.”



















































Source/Fuente: www.youtube.com





Friday, October 9, 2015

MUS/GralInt-John Lennon - (Just Like) Starting Over (promo video 1980) (Remembering John Lennon´s 75th birthday)

The following information is used for educational purposes only.




John Lennon - (Just Like) Starting Over (promo video 1980)


Gabriel Pereira


Published on Nov 1, 2013

John Lennon and Yoko Ono filmed a video to promote his new album, Double Fantasy, in the City of New York, November 26, 1980. Filming began in Central Park, then moved to a gallery in SoHo in scenes that come in a white room, first with street clothes after the clothes are removed, and make love.
The song chosen for the video promo was (Just Like) Starting Over.
The confirmation was canceled before the fateful death of Lennon on December 8, little or nothing to come to light in this recording.
From me to try to put together what had material, this promo video (Just Like) Starting Over was canceled. Hope you like it!.

John Lennon y Yoko Ono filmaron un video para promocionar su nuevo álbum, Double Fantasy,en la Ciudad de Nueva York, el 26 de noviembre de 1980. La filmación comenzó en Central Park, luego se trasladó a una galería en SoHo en las escenas en que llegarían a una habitación blanca, primero con ropa de calle,después se sacan la ropa, y hacen el amor.
La canción elegida para el video promo fue (Just Like) Starting Over.
La filmación fue cancelada ante la fatídica muerte de Lennon el 8 de Diciembre,y poco y nada ha salido a luz de esa grabación.
De mi parte trate de armar con lo que había de material, ese video promo de (Just Like) Starting Over fue cancelado. ¡Espero que les guste!




































Lyrics:



"(Just Like) Starting Over"

Our life together is so precious together,
We have grown - we have grown,
Although our love is still special,
Let's take our chance and fly away somewhere alone,

It's been so long since we took the time,
No-one's to blame,
I know time flies so quickly,
But when I see you darling,
It's like we both are falling in love again,
It'll be just like starting over - starting over,

Everyday we used to make it love,
Why can't we be making love nice and easy,
It's time to spread our wings and fly,
Don't let another day go by my love,
It'll be just like starting over - starting over,

Why don't we take off alone,
Take a trip far, far away,
We'll be together on our own again,
Like we used to in the early days,
Well, well, well darling,

It's been so long since we took the time,
No-one's to blame,
I know time flies so quickly,
But when I see you darling,
It's like we both are falling in love again,
It'll be just like starting over - starting over,

Everyday we used to make it love,
Why can't we be making love nice and easy,
It's time to spread our wings and fly,
Don't let another day go by my love,
It'll be just like starting over - starting over,

Our life together is so precious together,
We have grown - we have grown,
Although our love is still special,
Let's take our chance and fly away somewhere alone.





Source: www.youtube.com/http://www.azlyrics.com/lyrics/johnlennon/justlikestartingover.html

Wednesday, October 7, 2015

MUS/GralInt-Robin Thicke - Blurred Lines ft. T.I., Pharrell

The following information is used for educational purposes only.












Robin Thicke - Blurred Lines ft. T.I., Pharrell


















































Lyrics:

"Blurred Lines"
(feat. T.I. & Pharrell Williams)

[Intro - Pharrell & Robin Thicke:]
Everybody get up, WOO!
Everybody get up, WOO!
Hey, hey, hey
Hey, hey, hey
WOO!
Hey, hey, hey
WOO!

[Verse 1 - Robin Thicke:]
If you can't hear what I'm trying to say
If you can't read from the same page
Maybe I'm going deaf
Maybe I'm going blind
Maybe I'm out of my mind
[Pharrell:] Everybody get up

[Bridge - Robin Thicke:]
Ok, now he was close
Tried to domesticate you
But you're an animal
Baby, it's in your nature
Just let me liberate you
You don't need no papers
That man is not your maker
And that's why I'm gon' take a

[Hook - Robin Thicke:]
Good girl
I know you want it
I know you want it
I know you want it
You're a good girl
Can't let it get past me
You're far from plastic
Talk about getting blasted
I hate these blurred lines
I know you want it
I know you want it
I know you want it
But you're a good girl
The way you grab me
Must wanna get nasty
Go ahead, get at me
[Pharrell:] Everybody get up

[Verse 2 - Robin Thicke:]
What do they make dreams for
When you got them jeans on
What do we need steam for
You the hottest bitch in this place
I feel so lucky,
Hey, hey, hey
You wanna hug me
Hey, hey, hey
What rhymes with hug me?
Hey, hey, hey
Hey!

[Bridge]

[Hook]

[Verse 3 - T.I.:]
Hustle Gang Homie
One thing I ask of you
Lemme be the one you back that ass up to
From Malibu to Paris boo
Had a bitch, but she ain't bad as you
So, hit me up when you pass through
I'll give you something big enough to tear your ass in two
Swag on 'em even when you dress casual
I mean, it's almost unbearable
In a hundred years not dare would I
Pull a Pharcyde, let you pass me by
Nothin' like your last guy, he too square for you
He don't smack that ass and pull your hair like that
So I'm just watching and waitin'
For you to salute the true big pimpin'
Not many women can refuse this pimping
I'm a nice guy, but don't get confused, this pimpin'

[Breakdown - Robin Thicke:]
Shake your rump
Get down, get up-a
Do it like it hurt, like it hurt
What you don't like work
Hey!

[Verse 4 - Robin Thicke:]
Baby, can you breathe
I got this from Jamaica
It always works for me
Dakota to Decatur
No more pretending
Cause now you're winning
Here's our beginning
I always wanted a

[Hook - Robin Thicke]

[Outro - Pharrell & Robin Thicke:]
Everybody get up, WOO!
Everybody get up
Hey, hey, hey
Hey, hey, hey
Hey, hey, hey





Source: www.youtube.com/http://www.azlyrics.com/lyrics/robinthicke/blurredlines.html

MUS/GralInt-Capital Cities - Safe And Sound (Official Video)

The following information is used for educational purposes only.







Capital Cities - Safe And Sound (Official Video)





































Lyrics:





"Safe And Sound"

I could lift you up
I could show you what you wanna see
And take you where you wanna be

You could be my luck
Even if the sky is falling down
I know that we'll be safe and sound

We're safe and sound

I could fill your cup
You know my river won't evaporate
This world we still appreciate

You could be my luck
Even in a hurricane of frowns
I know that we'll be safe and sound

Safe and sound
We're safe and sound
Safe and sound
We're safe and sound
Hold your ground
We're safe and sound
Safe and sound

I could show you love
In a tidal wave of mystery
You'll still be standing next to me

You could be my luck
Even if we're six feet underground
I know that we'll be safe and sound

We're safe and sound

Safe and sound
Safe and sound
Hold your ground
Safe and sound

I could lift you up
I could show you what you wanna see
And take you where you wanna be

You could be my luck
Even if the sky is falling down
I know that we'll be safe and sound

I could lift you up
I could show you what you wanna see
And take you where you wanna be

You could be my luck
Even if the sky is falling down
I know that we'll be safe and sound

We're safe and sound
We're safe and sound
We're safe and sound
We're safe and sound

Safe and sound
We're safe and sound
Safe and sound
We're safe and sound
Hold your ground
We're safe and sound
Safe and sound
We're safe and sound

















Source: www.youtube.com/http://www.azlyrics.com/lyrics/capitalcities/safeandsound.html





MUS/GralInt-John Legend - All of Me

The following information is used for educational purposes only.






John Legend - All of Me











































Lyrics:


"All Of Me"

[Verse 1:]
What would I do without your smart mouth?
Drawing me in, and you kicking me out
You've got my head spinning, no kidding, I can't pin you down
What's going on in that beautiful mind
I'm on your magical mystery ride
And I'm so dizzy, don't know what hit me, but I'll be alright

[Pre-Chorus:]
My head's under water
But I'm breathing fine
You're crazy and I'm out of my mind

[Chorus:]
'Cause all of me
Loves all of you
Love your curves and all your edges
All your perfect imperfections
Give your all to me
I'll give my all to you
You're my end and my beginning
Even when I lose I'm winning
'Cause I give you all of me
And you give me all of you, oh oh

[Verse 2:]
How many times do I have to tell you
Even when you're crying you're beautiful too
The world is beating you down, I'm around through every mood
You're my downfall, you're my muse
My worst distraction, my rhythm and blues
I can't stop singing, it's ringing, in my head for you

[Pre-Chorus:]
My head's under water
But I'm breathing fine
You're crazy and I'm out of my mind

[Chorus:]
'Cause all of me
Loves all of you
Love your curves and all your edges
All your perfect imperfections
Give your all to me
I'll give my all to you
You're my end and my beginning
Even when I lose I'm winning
'Cause I give you all of me
And you give me all of you, oh oh

[Bridge:]
Give me all of you
Cards on the table, we're both showing hearts
Risking it all, though it's hard

[Chorus:]
'Cause all of me
Loves all of you
Love your curves and all your edges
All your perfect imperfections
Give your all to me
I'll give my all to you
You're my end and my beginning
Even when I lose I'm winning
'Cause I give you all of me
And you give me all of you

I give you all of me
And you give me all of you, oh oh






Source: www.youtube.com/http://www.azlyrics.com/lyrics/johnlegend/allofme.html

Sunday, October 4, 2015

BRAIN/HEALTH/PSYCH/GralInt-What Negative Thinking Does to Your Brain

The following information is used for educational purposes only.




What Negative Thinking Does to Your Brain


If you’ve ever found yourself trapped in a seemingly endless loop of negative thinking, or wondered why you fixate on a stray rude comment but easily forget compliments, you may have a culprit to blame: evolution.



According to Rick Hanson, Ph.D., a neuropsychologist, founder of the Wellspring Institute for Neuroscience and Contemplative Wisdom, and New York Times best-selling author, humans are evolutionarily wired with a negativity bias. Our minds naturally focus on the bad and discard the good. It was much more important for our ancestors to avoid threats than to collect rewards: An individual who successfully avoided a threat would wake up the next morning and have another opportunity to collect a reward, but an individual who didn’t avoid the threat would have no such opportunity.

Thus, the human brain evolved to focus on threats. Millennials are no stranger to stress and depression, especially when it’s work related—a recent study reported that around 20 percent of Millennials sought out help or advice in the workplace for depression—a higher percentage than any other generation. According to the Status of Women in the States report from the Institute for Women’s Policy Research, Millennial women ages 18-34 report an average of 4.9 days of poor mental health per month, while Millennial men report an average of 3.6 poor mental health days. Our brains are highly attuned to stress, even when such stress is of the mundane variety and not at all life threatening.

"Negative stimuli produce more neural activity than do equally intense (e.g., loud, bright) positive ones, Hanson writes on his website. “They are also perceived more easily and quickly. For example, people in studies can identify angry faces faster than happy ones; even if they are shown these images so quickly (just a tenth of a second or so) that they cannot have any conscious recognition of them, the ancient fight-or-flight limbic system of the brain will still get activated by the angry faces.”

Hanson describes the brain as like "Velcro for negative experiences and Teflon for positive ones." While some individuals may be inherently more optimistic than others, it’s generally true that in order for positive experiences to “stick” in our brains as well as negative ones do, these positive experiences need to be held in our consciousness for a longer period of time.

“The alarm bell of your brain — the amygdala (you’ve got two of these little almond-shaped regions, one on either side of your head) — uses about two-thirds of its neurons to look for bad news: it’s primed to go negative,” writes Hanson. “Once it sounds the alarm, negative events and experiences get quickly stored in memory — in contrast to positive events and experiences, which usually need to be held in awareness for a dozen or more seconds to transfer from short-term memory buffers to long-term storage."

HOW NEGATIVE THINKING CHANGES THE BRAIN


The more that an individual’s thought patterns trend negative and slip into rumination—continually turning over a situation in one’s mind and focusing on its negative aspects—the easier it becomes to return automatically to these thought patterns.

That’s not so great for our health. According to a blog post on Psychology Today, ruminating can damage the neural structures that regulate emotions, memory, and feelings. Even when our stress and worry is completely hypothetical and not based on any real or current situation, the amygdala and the thalamus (which helps communicate sensory and motor signals) aren’t able to differentiate this hypothetical stress from the kind that actually needs to be listened to.

Cortisol, a stress hormone, breaks down the hippocampus, the part of the brain that helps form new memories. Most people experience a peak of cortisol in the morning, but it can also spike throughout the day in response to stress. The more cortisol that’s released in response to negative experiences and thoughts, the more difficult it can become, over time, to form new positive memories.

In neuroscience, the expression “neurons that fire together, wire together” describes “experience-dependent neuroplasticity”—essentially, the concept that our brains are shaped by our thoughts and experiences. According to Hanson, the synapses in our brains that fire frequently become more sensitive. Our experiences and thoughts can lead to the growth of new synapses and even change our genes, altering the very structure of our brain. Or, as Hanson writes, “the brain takes its shape from what the mind rests upon.”

If you’re prone to negative thinking, this might seem disheartening. It’s easy to assume that we have no control over our thoughts. After all, they often pop up out of nowhere, and when rumination takes hold, it can be difficult to break its grip (I would know, I’m an accomplished ruminator). But the good news—and the basis of much of Hanson’s work—is that it is possible to change our thought patterns and even “hardwire happiness” into our brains (which is the title of Hanson’s 2013 book).

SHIFTING NEGATIVE THOUGHT PATTERNS

Edward Selby, Ph.D., suggests in a post on Psychology Today that engaging an activity that fully occupies the mind, such a crossword puzzle, can be helpful in terms of breaking out of ruminative thought patterns.

Mindfulness—a non-judgmental awareness of moment-to-moment experience—and a regular meditation practice have been proven to be immensely valuable in shifting negative thought patterns and brain activity. One study published in Cognitive Therapy and Research in 2014 found that decentering, or stepping back to “observe thoughts and feelings as temporary and objective events in the mind,” can help mediate the effects of rumination in individuals with depression. Mindfulness Based Stress Reduction (MBSR), developed by Jon Kabat-Zinn, founder of the Stress Reduction Clinic at the University of Massachusetts Medical School, teaches individuals to train their minds to cope with stress more skillfully (I discovered Rick Hanson through Karen Sothers, who teaches MBSR at the Scripps Institute for Integrative Medicine in San Diego, California).

Meditating regularly (there are apps for that: here’s a list) can not only help shift negative thought patterns—it helps the brain focus its attention and even slow the loss of brain cells. For individuals struggling with depression, meditation won’t necessarily substitute for therapy and/or medication, but it can work as a complement. Hanson also recommends practicing gratitude (keeping a gratitude journal and writing in it each morning is one way to do so), which can help increase psychological wellbeing.






Source:http://www.stumbleupon.com/su/2FlkYt/:N4T7nssC:iTPXZtYC/www.attn.com/stories/2587/what-negative-thinking-does-your-brain

ECON/POL/GralInt-Insólitas conclusiones de la relación entre argentinos, dinero y felicidad

The following information is used for educational purposes only.




Insólitas conclusiones de la relación entre argentinos, dinero y felicidad

Un estudio muestra que la gente piensa que para ser rico hay que ser corrupto; además están de acuerdo con la redistribución, pero todos se consideran exceptuados de aportar.

Carlos Manzoni


LA NACION

DOMINGO 04 DE OCTUBRE DE 2015



Los argentinos miran más de lo debido el sueldo de sus compañeros de trabajo para considerarse conformes con su salario; creen que el dinero no hace la felicidad, pero sí mencionan el aspecto económico a la hora de explicar su infelicidad, y la mayoría está de acuerdo con un modelo redistributivo en el que se quite a los más ricos para repartir a los pobres, pero con una salvedad..., ninguno se considera pasible de recibir un recorte en sus ingresos puesto que nadie se autodefine como clase alta. Estas conclusiones no están solas; hay un manojo más de afirmaciones a las que se llega al analizar la relación de los habitantes de este país con el dinero y la satisfacción que tienen con sus vidas.


La radiografía de los argentinos y su vinculación amor/odio con el dinero o los aspectos económicos de su existencia surge del "4° Estudio sobre Felicidad, Relacionado con la Estructura Social", elaborado por la Universidad de Palermo (UP) y TNS Gallup, en el que participaron Gabriel Foglia, decano de la Facultad de Ciencias Económicas de la UP, y Cynthia Carbonell, directora de Proyectos de TNS Argentina.

TODOS QUIEREN SER ROBIN HOOD, PERO NADIE SE RECONOCE RICO

En la Argentina, la mayoría de los encuestados para el trabajo mencionado considera que están bien las políticas redistributivas en las que se les quita un poco a los más pudientes para repartir entre los más necesitados. Pero a la hora de autodefinirse de una determinada clase social, nadie se identifica con la clase más alta, que sería la pasible de recibir un recorte de sus ingresos para dar a los pobres. "Tanto los de clase alta como los de clase media y baja se consideran clase media", apunta Gabriel Foglia.

Carbonell destaca que en este cuarto estudio que hacen sobre la felicidad, lo que se empieza a notar es inconsistencia de la respuesta de la gente cuando se le pregunta si está de acuerdo con una política redistributiva. "Responden que sí, pero después nadie se reconoce como clase pudiente, aun aquellos que son claramente clase alta. Cada uno está de acuerdo en que alguien pague impuestos para una política redistributiva, siempre y cuando no sea él", concluye la especialista.

Nadie dice ser de clase alta


Consultados sobre en qué lugar de la estructura económica y social se ubicarían, la mitad de los argentinos dijo ser de clase media-media. Ningún entrevistado se identificó como perteneciente a la clase alta, y sólo 2% se autodefinió como de clase media-alta. "El 88% declaró pertenecer a la clase media o media-baja, y sólo 10% se identificó como clase baja", se especifica en el estudio.

En tanto, al cruzar estos datos con el nivel sociodemográfico de la muestra surge que entre aquellos que pertenecen al segmento ABC1, 88% se identificó como clase media o media-baja, y 4%, directamente como clase baja. En esta sintonía, 86% de los entrevistados pertenecientes al segmento D y E dijo pertenecer a segmentos medios de la sociedad.


El economista Martín Tetaz, autor del libro Casual Mente, dice que la distorsión de que todos piensen que son de clase media ocurre por un sesgo de representatividad. "No vivimos en grupos aleatorios representativos de toda la sociedad, sino en estratificaciones de personas de similar situación socioeconómica que la nuestra (los barrios) y tendemos a juntarnos con amigos y compañeros similares a nosotros. Y la verdad es que nos sentimos del promedio porque dentro de esos grupos estamos en el medio, aunque esos grupos sean una isla y no sean para nada representativos de la sociedad", analiza el especialista.

El dinero no se hace trabajando

Otro aspecto destacado es que en este país, la mayoría opina que aquellos que tienen dinero lo obtuvieron de manera "non sancta", básicamente de la mano de la corrupción y el fraude. "Por eso está mal visto ganar dinero", comenta Emilia Montero, coordinadora académica de Recursos Humanos de la Facultad de Ciencias Económicas de la UP.

"En lo que hace a los factores que explican el acceso a posiciones de privilegio, 24% de los encuestados lo atribuye al fraude o la corrupción. En segundo lugar aparece la herencia familiar (21%), en tercer lugar la educación (16%) y sólo el 13% identifica el estatus social con el esfuerzo", desgrana Montero.

Estas respuestas están muy vinculadas también con el hecho de que nadie se considera de clase alta y, por lo tanto, nadie cree que está en el segmento donde se delinque para ganar posición económica. "La misma clase alta, que no se considera alta, dice que se escala gracias a la corrupción y el fraude", acota Foglia.

La educación es siempre culpable, nunca benéfica

Relacionada con el punto anterior está otra parte del estudio, que ahonda en las causas por las que una persona es de clase alta y por qué una de clase baja no puede ascender. Tal como se dijo antes, el principal factor que los argentinos consideran a la hora de explicar por qué alguien es rico es la corrupción, cuando en países desarrollados ocupa ese sitial la educación. Sin embargo, cuando se pregunta por qué la gente que está en los estratos más desfavorecidos no progresa, sí se atribuye la "culpa" a la educación.

Carbonell dice que les sorprendió que el ascenso no estuviera asociado al estudio y sí a maneras ilícitas de obtener riqueza. "Lo curioso es que si se lo pregunta al revés, es decir, si se pregunta por qué una persona no sale de una clase menos favorecida, sí aparece como principal factor la falta de educación -explica la investigadora-. Es muy llamativo que en general, la educación se asocia sólo a no poder salir de la pobreza y me sorprendió negativamente que en el imaginario general se crea que, para crecer en la escala social, vale más la corrupción y no la educación."

Dime lo que gana tu compañero y te diré cuán feliz eres

Los argentinos son menos racionales de lo que se sospecha. Cuando se presenta la hipótesis de que podría ganar un sueldo de $ 8000 mientras que el compañero gana $ 6000, la mayoría se muestra más satisfecho que si se le da la opción de que los dos cobren $ 9000. "No parece una opción inteligente, sin embargo, así somos", acota Foglia.

Tetaz explica que importa más el ingreso relativo que el absoluto, la comparación con el otro. "La primera explicación para esto es que nos comparamos contra nuestros colegas o pares porque no tenemos idea de cuánto nos merecemos ganar; entonces miramos a los otros como referencia: si mis compañeros ganan 12.000 me pongo contento con 14.000 no porque me haga feliz que ellos ganen menos, sino porque pienso que 12.000 era lo que correspondía, y entonces estoy contento por ganar un poco más", dice.

La segunda hipótesis de Tetaz para esta respuesta es que, simplemente, el hombre es un animal social y todos los mamíferos se ordenan grupalmente en torno de alguna jerarquía particular que determina el orden de prioridad en el acceso a los recursos de supervivencia y reproducción. "En esos ordenamientos sociales sólo importa la posición relativa en el grupo y es probable que eso explique por qué preferimos ganar menos si ello mejora nuestra posición relativa en la oficina", concluye el economista.

El dinero no hace la felicidad, pero si me falta soy infeliz

En un estudio preliminar sobre bienestar subjetivo, también elaborado por la UP y TNS Gallup, se destaca que el dinero no está entre las primeras razones que las personas esgrimen para explicar por qué son felices. En tanto, en un contraste un poco contradictorio, sí aparece la cuestión económica a la hora de explicar la infelicidad.

"Al preguntarle a los encuestados sobre razones por las que se consideran felices, 4 de cada 10 se refirieron a la familia y los seres queridos, mientras que sólo 3 de cada 10 hicieron mención a estar muy bien económicamente... En cambio, entre las razones más mencionadas por los que declaran ser infelices se destacan problemas económicos...", se detalla en el informe.

Tetaz subraya al respecto que el economista Richard Easterlin demostró hace 35 años que en los países de más alto PBI per cápita, la gente no era más feliz que en los países que tenían un PBI per cápita más bajo. "Pero [la economista] Carol Graham mostró luego que había un «umbral de ingresos", y que los ingresos sí importaban hasta que se llegaba a un ingreso de clase media, pero que luego ya no existía relación. Por esa razón, aunque más ingresos no te hacen más feliz, si te faltan los ingresos sufrís infelicidad", explica.







Fuente: LA NACION | Economía

ECON/BUS/POL/GralInt-How Business Community Institutions Can Help Fight Corruption∗

The following information is used for educational purposes only.



How Business Community Institutions Can Help Fight Corruption∗


Avinash Dixit, Princeton University

This version March 11, 2015

Abstract

Collective action by the business community to counter corruption in the award of
government licenses and contracts is analyzed, by analogy with contract enforcement
institutions studied by economic historians and contract law scholars. The suggested
anti-corruption institution comprises a no-bribery norm, a system to detect violations,
and a multilateral ostracism penalty upon conviction in a tribunal. In combination with
formal state law, a business institution of sufficient quality—probability of detection
and severity of punishment—can eliminate corruption; a less good institution helps
reduce it. The legal and communal institutions together achieve substantially better
outcomes than either by itself.

JEL classification codes: D02, D73, K42, P37, P48

Author’s contact information

E-mail: dixitak@princeton.edu
Web page: https://www.princeton.edu/ e
dixitak/home/wrkps.html
Mail: Department of Economics, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ 08544, USA

∗This paper was written during a very pleasant month as a Visiting Research Fellow in the Development
Economics department (DECVP) of the World Bank, and presented at the Bank’s ABCDE Conference in
Washington, DC, June 2-3, 2014. I thank audience members at the conference, and subsequent seminar
audiences at the Blavatnik School of Government, Oxford University, the 2014 meetings of the Hong Kong
Economic Association, and the Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton, for their comments. I also thank
Toni Adlerman, Tito Cordella, Aslı Demirg¨u¸c-Kunt, Varun Gauri, Stuti Khemani, Aart Kraay, and Francesca
Recanatini for useful conversations, and Kaushik Basu and Dani Rodrik for valuable comments on a previous
draft. Of course the assertions and views expressed here are my own, and not those of the World Bank or
any of its staff.


1 Introduction

Corruption in dealings between business firms and government officials and politicians is
a complex problem that needs to be tackled from multiple angles. Most anti-corruption
strategies that have been proposed in policy forums and studied by researchers have two
features. First, they are controlled by governments: either the general apparatus of police
and courts, or special anti-corruption agencies. Second, their main target is what may be
termed the demand side, namely detection and punishment of officials who demand bribes,
whether for granting some special treatment to those who meet their demand, or as extra
extortion payments for taking actions to which the applicant was entitled either without
charge or for some nominal fee. Indeed, some researchers have suggested an asymmetric
treatment where punishment for the latter kind of bribery should fall entirely on the demand
side; suppliers of such bribes should not be punished, or should even be rewarded, for whistleblowing.
See Basu (2011), and formal modeling and extensions in Basu, Basu, Cordella and
Varoudakis (2014).

The government’s formal anti-corruption efforts face a very basic and formidable obstacle.
Many officials and politicians, and often even the government in aggregate, stand to gain from
corruption. The financial gains are large; political gains from reducing corruption may not
be large enough to offset these. Therefore anti-corruption measures and their enforcement
are often halfhearted, and any actions by one branch of the government are obstructed by
other branches or departments with parallel or independent powers. The incentives of the
business community as a whole are better aligned to resist corruption. In some situations
business may collude with government officials to increase costs of public projects so both
of these parties gain at the expense of the taxpayers. But on the whole the politicians’ and
officials’s take is a direct hit to the bottom line of business.

A bribe acts as a tax on business, and an uncertain and inefficient tax, that reduces the
incentive to invest and innovate; Ayyagari, Demirg¨u¸c-Kunt and Maksimovic (2014) provide
evidence bearing on this. Some may argue that business will simply pass on such a tax to
consumers through higher prices, but such recovery will in general be much less than full.
If the bribe is for a permit to operate the business per se, that is a fixed cost, and does
not alter the pricing decision. Any market power would already have been exercised to the
same extent and reflected in prices even without the existence of a bribe, so the bribe is a
pure subtraction from profit. A payment that affects marginal cost will impact prices. But
again, if the original price was optimally chosen to maximize profit, the added cost of the
bribe can only lower the net profit.1 There are conditions pertaining to the elasticity of the
slope of market demand for an oligopolistic industry, under which a higher marginal cost
leads to such a large increases in the equilibrium price that each firm’s profit goes up; see
Seade (1983) and Dixit (1986). However, these circumstances are unlikely to be relevant
in the present context. If they were, the oligopolists would have many more plausible and
legitimate avenues to raise their costs. For example, they could arrange some costly industrywide
regulation that even purports to serve a social purpose such as health promotion or
environment protection, instead of relying on bribery. And one never hears businesspeople
propose anything resembling bribery as a way of increasing profits for whole industries!
Thus we may conclude that a corrupt system is likely to reduce profitability and growth
prospects for the business community as a whole. Of course a firm that wins a government
license or contract through bribery will benefit at the expense of other competing firms.
Therefore individual firms are tempted to engage in bribery even when the business community
as a whole stands to lose from the corrupt system. This is a prisoners’ dilemma:
individually rational choices lead to a collectively bad outcome. Like all such dilemmas,
collective action is needed to resolve it.

Here I explore the potential of one such non-governmental institution that operates on
the supply side by detecting and punishing givers of bribes, following an initial suggestion in
Dixit (2013). If several major and respected firms and businesspeople can become persuaded
to take a leadership role in launching and sustaining a collective anti-bribe-giving effort, then
they, in alliance with some political and governmental leaders, have a better chance of success
than either side on its own.
The concept is similar to the institutions of contract enforcement studied by Greif (1993),
Bernstein (1992) and others. Their communities of businesspeople or traders sustain a norm
of good behavior in contractual performance using a threat of multilateral punishment. Even
though any two given members of the community may not have sufficiently frequent bilateral
interaction to support an honest equilibrium outcome in their repeated game, the prospect
that if member B cheats in dealing with member A, then C, D, E, ... will punish B on A’s
1


If the profit is
Π = max
p
(p − c) D(p)
in obvious notation, then by the envelope theorem
∂Π/∂c = −D(p

) < 0 where p ∗ is the profit-maximizing price. 3 behalf in their future interactions makes it a repeated game for B in his dealings with the community as a whole. The mechanism requires the community to have a reliable apparatus for detecting and investigating violations of the norm, and a credible and sufficiently severe punishment for proven contract violations and defiance of any stipulated remedies. The usual punishment is ostracism, which is very drastic since it wipes out the industry-specific capital of the guilty party and essentially takes away his livelihood. The prospect of efficient application of this severe punishment keeps most participants honest; there are few contractual disputes and the punishment has to be inflicted only rarely. In the case of Greif’s Maghribi traders, the detection apparatus was the system of communication—letters exchanged among the members of this relatively small and closed community. The enforcement of ostracism was credible because it was more costly for a member to enter into a relationship with an ostracized trader than one with a good reputation— the former feared no further punishment and was therefore more likely to cheat. In the case of Bernstein’s diamond merchants, detection is simple because an aggrieved member brings a complaint to the arbitration tribunal, which can investigate it rapidly and efficiently using the members’ experience and detailed inside knowledge of the industry. In the context of corruption, the norm would be not to give bribes to public officials in order to win licenses or permits, or to speed up the process of getting these. The sanction would be that any businessperson who is found to have violated this norm will be ostracized by the rest of the community. Since the winner of a license will need contact with many other members of the community of various essential purposes—supply, subcontracting, marketing, trade credit from other firms, longer-term credit from banks and other financial institutions, accounting services, and so on—a boycott from all or even many of these providers will severely reduce the values of the illicitly-won license and of future business opportunities. If this threat is sufficiently severe, winning the license by bribery becomes worthless. The model of Section 2.4 derives the conditions for this to work. I find that in combination with the government’s own demand-side enforcement efforts, it can make a significant contribution to reducing the level of corruption. At first the scheme may seem too idealistic or even na¨ıve to be practical. But there are some closely related precedents of collective action by the business community that have achieved some measure of success. Therefore I believe it deserves further study and even some experiments in implementation. 4 I should emphasize that I do not expect such a scheme to achieve in real life anywhere near the 100% success it can under certain conditions in the theoretical model of this paper. However, the problem is so pervasive and costly for economic development that even a 50% or even 25% success is worth having. Waiting for 100% merely guarantees getting 0%. 1.1 Practical Precedents Community activists in India have attempted to counter petty bribery by meeting demands with a specially printed zero-rupee note.2 The idea is partly to shame the official demanding a bribe, but more importantly, making him aware that the resisting client belongs to an organization, so any reprisal against him will have more serious consequences for the official than if the client were an isolated and unsupported individual. This institution claims to have achieved some success, but hard statistical evidence to support these claims awaits serious research. Other organized private efforts to increase anti-bribery compliance include TRACE International; see their web site http://www.traceinternational.org . Even more remarkable is the Sicilian community organization AddioPizzo that has attempted, with some success, to resist the Mafia’s extortion. The collective action has made it harder for the Mafia to target retribution that they would have easily inflicted on any individual unorganized resisters. See the account and analysis in Superti (2009). Business leadership in corporate governance reform has a long and distinguished history. To give just one prominent example, J. Pierpont Morgan and his partner Elbert Gary who founded Federal Steel “took the then unusual step of issuing quarterly reports” because “both men believed that corporations issuing publicly traded securities had to account for their financial performance” (Strouse 2000, p. 398). Only later was the idea picked up by the progressive movement and made into a legislated requirement. Prominent firms in modern sectors of India and some other developing countries are similarly taking leading roles in reforming corporate governance, albeit with limited success so far (Khanna and Palepu, 2004). A similar community effort to fight corruption would be a valuable and welcome extension of these initiatives. 2 See http://www.5thpillar.org and http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zero rupee note. 5 1.2 Literature on Corruption

The literature on corruption is too huge to survey here. I will only mention the seminal
work of Becker and Stigler (1974) and Rose-Ackerman (1978), and the surveys by Aidt
(2003) and Rose-Ackerman (2011). In all this work, anti-corruption policies are assumed to
be the government’s job, using its formal legal apparatus. The modeling is very detailed and
sophisticated. But my focus is on the extra role a non-governmental business community
association can play; therefore I will keep the government side quite simple and in a reduced
form.

2 A Formal Model

Suppose a permit or license or contract (henceforth called “license” to avoid constant repetition)
lasting one period has value L to a person or firm (henceforth simply “firm” for
brevity). I assume L to be exogenous and the same for all potential recipients, like the
common value assumption in auction theory; variations and extensions are left for future
research. A bureaucracy, which I shall model as a single decision-maker called “the bureaucrat,”
decides whether to grant the license. I shall consider both the competitive case where
there is only one license and many firms would like to get it, and the non-competitive case
where any qualified person or firm can have one. Many other cases can be considered: the
license can last more than one period, it may be partially competitive in the sense that its
value to one firm depends on how many others have one. These are left for future research.
There will be two key variables in the model: the bribe B relative to the value of the
license, denoted by β = B/L, and the degree of favoritism shown by the bureaucrat to a firm
that pays a bribe, which I shall model as a ratio π = pB/p0, where p0 is the probability of
getting the license without paying a bribe and pB the probability of getting it with a bribe.
The cases p0 = 0 and pB = 1 are not excluded a priori. Both β and π are endogenous, to
be determined in the various cases under consideration. Other formulations, such as faster
service to a bribe-paying firm, are conceivable and should yield qualitatively similar results.
I model the bribe as a kickback, i.e. it is to be paid if and only if the firm wins the license.
Modeling it as an advance payment without refunds to losers (like an all-pay auction) changes
some of the algebra but the qualitative results remain the same.
Note also that the model is “partial” or “reduced-form.” I am considering the interaction
between just one firm and the bureaucracy. Considering all firms together will enable some
of the above parameters to become endogenous variables; for example, if n identical firms
are competing for just one license, in absence of bribery we could have a random allocation
mechanism, so p0 = 1/n where n is the number of firms. But the main points can be made
without the added considerations like solution of a general game equilibrium with all firms
and the bureaucracy as players, so I will keep everything as simple as possible.
I begin with separate treatments of the bureaucrat’s decision (the “demand side” of
corruption) and a firm’s decision (the “supply side”), and then put the two together to
characterize the overall equilibrium or outcome of their interaction.

2.1 The Demand Side

The bureaucrat would of course like to extract as much of the value of the license as possible.
What constrains him is the risk of being detected and punished. Detection need not be the
result of monitoring by a formal anti-corruption agency or some other government body.
It could come about from investigative journalism, or complaints by aggrieved client firms
or internal or external whistleblowers. I specify all this monitoring technology in a simple
reduced form, writing the probability of detection as a function D(β, π). The idea is that
if the fraction of the license fee that is demanded as a bribe is small, it is unlikely to elicit
complaints or whistle-blowing, but if the fraction is higher, such activities are more likely.
Similarly, if the probability of winning the license with bribery is substantially higher than
getting it without bribery, this is more likely to be blatant and visible to anti-corruption
inspectors or investigative journalists. I assume a linear form
D(β, π) = g β + h (π − 1). (1)
This makes the calculations simpler and yields insights based on plausible numerical values;
the qualitative results will persist for more general functional forms. Of course a probability
cannot be a linear function over a large domain, but linearity can be a locally valid
approximation, and the qualitative results will generalize to plausible nonlinear functions.
Suppose that, when detected, the bureaucrat is punished by having to give up the bribed
amount and in addition paying a fine F. Then his expected payoff from the bribe is
EP = D(β, π) (−F) + [1 − D(β, π)] β L
= − [g β + h (π − 1) ] F + { 1 − [ β + h (π − 1) ] } β L . (2)
7
Setting this expression equal to a constant c and solving for π, we get the equation of a
typical iso-expected-payoff (IEP) contour:
π = 1 +
1
h
"
− g β +
β L − c
F + β L #
(3)
Then
∂π
∂β =
1
h
"
− g +
(F + c) L
(F + β L)
2
#
(4)
and


∂β2
= −
2 (F + c) L
2
(F + β L)
3
< 0 . Also ∂π ∂c = − 1 h (F + β L) < 0 . Thus the IEP contours are concave, and those lower down correspond to higher expected payoff levels. Figure 1 shows some of these contours. The intuition is that an increase in the favoritism variable π holding the rent extraction ratio β constant (i.e. a vertically upward move in the figure) always makes the bureaucrat worse off by raising the risk of detection, but an increase in β holding π constant (i.e. a horizontal rightward move) creates a tradeoff between bribe revenue and risk of detection, therefore the contours peak in that direction. **** Figure 1 about here **** Of course the bureaucrat can always act honestly and award the license to any qualified applicant in the non-competitive case and the best-qualified applicant in the competitive case. This will yield him zero expected payoff in the formula (2).3 Therefore a corrupt bureaucrat will choose only points in the region in Figure 1 below the contour labeled EP0 where c = 0; this is shown shaded. Note that it starts at the point where β = 0 and π = 1, i.e. the “honesty point” with no bribes and no favoritism. 3That is simply the choice of origin of the expected payoff. It would matter in models that considered government policies of paying efficiency wages or similar bonuses to deter corruption, but that is not my focus here. 8 2.2 The Supply Side without the Business Institution

An applicant for the license is willing to pay the bribe if pB (L − B) ≥ p0 L.
4 Using the
definitions
π = pB / p0, β = B/L ,
this becomes
π ≥ 1/(1 − β). (5)
The boundary of this, defined by an equality in (5), is an increasing convex curve in (β, π)
space, passing through the honesty point (0,1) and asymptotic to the vertical line β = 1.
Figure 2 shows this curve, and the shaded region above it is the set of points satisfying (5)
where the firm is willing to pay the bribe.
**** Figure 2 about here ****

2.3 The Outcome without the Business Institution

Figure 3 brings together these curves. On or above the curve labeled π = 1/(1−β), applicants
are willing to pay the bribes demanded. At points on or below the curve labeled EP0, the
bureaucracy has positive expected payoff from its corrupt strategy. The intersection of these
two regions, shown shaded, is therefore the feasible set. I assume that the bureaucrat states
the terms of the bribe demand, to maximize his expected payoff EP subject to feasibility.5
This occurs at the point B of tangency between the frontier of the feasible set (5) and an
IEP contour labeled EP*. Note that at B we have 0 < β < 1 and π > 1.
**** Figure 3 about here ****
The bureaucrat’s choice of π may be subject to one other constraint. The firm’s competence
or quality may imply that in a bribe-free setting it would get the license with a given
probability p0 that is not under the bureaucrat’s control. Since pB ≤ 1, the bureaucrat’s
choice must satisfy π ≤ 1/p0, i.e. it must be on or below a horizontal line like the one labeled
U in Figure 3. I have shown a case where this line is above the point B and therefore this
4
In the alternative case of an all-pay bribe, this would change to pB L − B ≥ p0 L. Readers who prefer
that formulation can easily rework the algebra and the figures.
5This seems more realistic in the context, but alternative solution concepts like Nash bargaining, or the
bribe-giver’s leadership to make the offer, will have qualitatively similar properties.
9
constraint is irrelevant, but if p0 is high enough the constraint may bind; then the solution
will be at the corner where the line intersects the firm’s willingness-to-pay frontier.
Both curves have the honesty point in common, and the only way the government’s
detection and punishment system can eliminate corruption is if there is a corner solution at
this point. For that to happen, the EP0 contour has to be flatter than the frontier of the
feasible set. The slope of the former is given by (4) setting c = 0 and β = 0, and that of the
latter can be found by differentiating its equation π = 1/(1 − β). This yields the condition
for a corner solution:
1
h

− g +
L
F

< 1, or F / L > 1/(g + h) (6)
Let us consider plausible numerical values. To make the condition (6) easier to satisfy, g
and h should be as high as possible. The most we can expect for g is a value like 2 (which
means that a bureaucrat who demands half the value of the license for his bribe is sure to be
caught). For h, about 0.1 seems as high as we can expect (which means that a bureaucrat
who favors bribe givers by a factor of 10 is sure to be caught). Then the condition becomes
F > 0.476 L: even with the optimistic assumptions about detection probabilities, fines have
to be close to half the value of the license. Financial fines of this magnitude seem infeasible in
cases of highly valuable licenses or contracts, because bureaucrats typically would not have
that much wealth to be confiscated. Unless a regime can impose non-monetary penalties that
are equivalently sufficiently harsh—long imprisonments or even death—demand side policies
will be insufficient to eliminate corruption. The best that can be done is to increase F as high
as possible, lowering and flattening the IEP curves and thereby shifting the bureaucracy’s
tangency optimum to the south-west (with lower β and π) along the boundary of the clients’
participation constraint. This is essentially the same solution as we have from Becker (1968)
for deterrence of crime in general.

2.4 The Supply Side with the Business Institution

Now suppose the business community forms an institution that can detect and punish firms
that pay bribes. The punishment consists of ostracism that reduces the values of the current
license and of future opportunities. Suppose that when a firm is convicted of bribery by
a tribunal of the business community, the value of the license falls from L to θ L, and the
continuation value of being in the business falls from V to φ V , where θ and φ lie between
0 and 1. A perfect punishment system would have θ = φ = 0, but I allow for a less than
perfect system as is likely to exist in reality. The detection mechanism is not perfect either;
let q denote the probability that a firm that is actually guilty of bribery will be convicted
by its peers in the association, and r the probability that an innocent firm will be wrongly
convicted, where 1 > q > r > 0. Let δ denote the discount factor.

Note once again the “reduced form” nature of the model: the parameters q, r, θ and
φ are taken to be exogenous. A fully rigorous model would specify a detection technology
from which q and r emerge endogenously, and a repeated game that endogenizes θ and φ.
Unfortunately we have little intuitive understanding of the deep structural parameters, so to
get some insight into plausible numerical answers it is better to start with parameters that
do have intuitive magnitudes. Also, the reduced form enables me to capture the intuitively
appealing idea of partially effective enforcement (θ and φ strictly between 0 and 1); in most
tractable structural models, enforcement is either perfect (θ = φ = 0) or totally ineffective
(θ = φ = 1).

Kingston (2008) constructs a structural model where a no-bribe equilibrium is sustained
in a repeated relationship by trade links among the bribers, but does not consider any
interaction with the formal state law and does not obtain numerical magnitudes. Thus his
paper and this one offer usefully complementary models.
In reality, q can be an increasing function of β and π similar to the supply-side detection
probability function (1) above; I will omit this algebraic complication.
Consider one firm’s decision whether to pay a bribe. By the standard recursion reasoning,
it is willing to comply with the bureaucrat’s demand if
V = (1 − q) [ pB (L − B) + δ V ] + q [ pB (θL − B) + δ φV ]
≥ (1 − r) [ p0 L + δ V ] + r [ p0 θL + δ φV ]
The equality implies
V = pB
[(1 − q) + θ q] L − B
1 − δ (1 − q + φ q)
and the inequality implies
p0 L [1 − r (1 − θ)] ≤ pB {L [1 − q (1 − θ)] − B} − δ V (q − r) (1 − φ).
11
The latter simplifies to
π ≥
1 − r (1 − θ)
1 − q (1 − θ) − β
1 − δ + δ q (1 − φ)
1 − δ + δ r (1 − φ)
, (7)
using the same notation π = pB/p0 and β = B/L as before.
Introduce the abbreviations
m = [1 − r (1 − θ)] 1 − δ + δ q (1 − φ)
1 − δ + δ r (1 − φ)
(8)
and
k = 1 − q (1 − θ). (9)
Obviously k < 1; also q > r ensures m > k, or m/k > 1. Then the condition (7) becomes
π ≥
m
k − β
(10)
**** Figure 4 about here ****
Figure 4 shows the frontier of this, defined by equality in (10), as the thick increasing
convex curve that starts at β = 0 and π = m/k, and is asymptotic to the vertical line β = k.
At the points on or above it, the firm is willing to pay the bribes demanded by the bureaucrat,
even at the risk of being detected and ostracized by the business community. Compare it
with the corresponding curve without the business institution, defined by equality in (5),
and shown in Figure 4 by the thinner curve. For given β, the ratio of π with the business
institution to that without is
m
1 − β
k − β
= m
"
1 +
1 − k
k − β
#
.
This equals m/k > 1 when β = 0, then increases monotonically as β increases, and → ∞
as β → k. Therefore the frontier of willingness to bribe with the institution lies uniformly
above that without the institution, as shown in Figure 4. The prospect of the community’s
punishment shrinks the region of the firm’s willingness to pay bribes.
Figure 5 brings together the bureaucrat’s IEP curves with the region where a firm is
willing to comply. Most importantly, it shows a case of an empty intersection between the
set of points where the firm is willing to pay the bribe and the set below the EP = 0 curve
where the bureaucracy has positive expected payoff (both these regions are shown shaded).
12
The bureaucracy does best by abandoning its attempts to demand bribes and being content
with zero payoff.
**** Figure 5 about here ****
We can now consider various ranges of parameters for the business community institution,
and compare the resulting numbers with the those for the state’s formal system on its own.
Table 1 shows a sample of such calculations. For each set of parameter values q, r, θ and
φ, the fine on the bureaucrat (as a fraction of the value of the license, F/L) that is needed
to achieve a corruption-free outcome is shown in the last column. The first row shows an
institution that does a good job of detection: the probability of convicting a guilty firm
is high (q = 0.75) and that of wrongful conviction of an innocent firm is low (r = 0.01).
But enforcement is poor: a convicted firm loses only 20% of its current and future profits
(θ = φ = 0.8). We have F/L = 0.145, much less than the 0.476 that was needed without
the business institution. The second row shows the opposite situation: good enforcement
(θ = φ = 0.1) but poor detection (q = 0.25, r = 0.1). Here we have F/L = 0.207, not
quite as good but still a big improvement over 0.476. In the third row we have case where
detection and enforcement are both intermediate; here we have a much better F/L = 0.101.
The final row shows an institution where both detection and enforcement are quite good.
Then the needed F/L is very low; the value 0.0046 means that for a license worth a million
dollars, a fine on the bureaucrat of only $4600 is needed to get a corruption-free outcome.
This good institution is still not quite as good as a combination of the best in the first two
rows (q = 0.75, r = 0.01, θ = φ = 0.1), but when I tried that, the required F/L had too
many starting zeroes!

Thus we see that the business institution in combination with the state’s imperfect legal
institutions is much more effective than the latter on its own. Also, the business institution’s
detection and enforcement capabilities appear to be mutually reinforcing (strategic
complements).
To get these numerical results, for each parameter set I start with a low value of F/L
and increase it gradually until the two regions in Figure 5 separate. For a fairly wide range
of parameters, at the separation point I find that β is in a neighborhood of 0.1. This is in a
sense the range of bribery that is most robust against punishments, and it is interesting to
note that in many countries with prevalent corruption 10% is indeed the “norm” for bribes.
13
Table 1: Sample numerical calculations for corruption-free equilibrium

Detection Enforcement Needed fine
q r θ φ F/L
Institution quality
Good detection 0.75 0.01 0.8 0.8 0.145
Good enforcement 0.25 0.10 0.1 0.1 0.207
Both medium 0.50 0.05 0.5 0.5 0.101
Both good 0.65 0.03 0.25 0.25 0.0046
Even if the intersection between the set of points where the firm is willing to pay the
bribe and the set below the EP = 0 curve where the bureaucracy has positive expected payoff
is non-empty, there is a third constraint that may come into play and rule out deviations
from a corruption-free equilibrium.
Suppose there are n firms, and their competence or quality is such that in a corruptionfree
equilibrium their probabilities of winning the license are pi
for i = 1, 2, . . . n. If the
license is exclusive and only one firm will get it, the pi must sum to 1. If it is not exclusive,
for example any restaurant that meets the health and safety standards will qualify for a
permit to operate, then there is no such restriction. Intermediate cases of congestion-like
interactions, where each pi depends on how many and which other firms receive the license,
are also possible. Anyway, I will take the pi as exogenous.
Firm i and the bureaucrat will be able to deviate and upset the candidate corruptionfree
equilibrium if they can find a corrupt deal, i.e. pair (β, π), that leaves both of them
better off. For this, the intersection of the firm’s willingness-to-bribe set, the bureaucrat’s
non-negative EP set, and the constraint π ≤ 1/pi must have a non-empty intersection.
Conversely, a corruption-free equilibrium requires an empty intersection for all firms. The
first two constraints are the same for all firms, but the third is firm-specific.6 A non-empty
intersection is most likely where that constraint is least relevant, i.e. for the firm with the
smallest pi
. Suppose this is firm 1. Then the corruption-free equilibrium requires an empty
6
It is easy to generalize the analysis to the case where the willingness-to-pay constraint is also firm-specific,
for example if the true and false conviction probabilities q and r are different for different firms. The only
added complication is a proliferation of cases and conditions for corruption-proofness.
14
intersection of the three constraints taking the third to be π ≤ 1/p1. Figure 6 shows such a
case.
**** Figure 6 about here ****
As intuition would suggest, the firm least likely to get the license in a corruption-free
situation is the one most likely to accede to a bribe demand. Conversely, firms that have
the best chances in the corruption-free situation are the best candidates for launching the
institution to sustain the clean equilibrium.
Thus far we have found conditions for none of the firms to violate the no-bribery norm,
given the threat of ostracism. Finally, we need to check that the threat is credible, i.e. that
other firms are willing to go along with the ostracism imposed on a firm that the community
has found guilty of bribery. This is in the context of Nash equilibrium: given that other
firms are complying with the ostracism, would it pay any one firm to break away and deal
with the miscreant? In emerging countries where our analysis is most relevant, inter-firm
dealings are on a relational basis, and the analysis of Greif (1993, Proposition 2, p. 535)
applies. Suppose firm A is already ostracized. It now fears no worse penalty; therefore it is
more likely to cheat in inter-firm dealings. To offset this temptation, Firm B contemplating
dealing firm A must give it more of the surplus from the deal. Therefore it is more costly
for B to deal with the ostracized firm A than with others such as say C, D, ... that have a
clear history. In other words, it is not in any firm’s interest to deviate from the community’s
sanctions on the original briber. Once the institution gets going, it will also develop its
culture that will reinforce the material incentive to conform with the sanctions.

2.5 Partial Reduction in Corruption

Even when the community institution is not good enough (the value of m is not high enough
and/or that of k is not low enough), it can make a contribution to reducing corruption in
combination with the formal legal apparatus. Consider the case shown in Figure 7. (Ignore
the dashed curves for the moment.) The set of (β, π) combinations where businesspeople
are willing to comply with demands for bribes has a non-empty intersection with the set
that gives positive expected payoff to the bureaucracy; this feasible set is shown shaded.
The outcome is at the point C of tangency between the feasible frontier and an IEP contour
labeled EP’. As was discussed in connection with Figures 3 and 6, if the worst-placed firm’s
competence or quality give it a probability p1 of getting the license in a bribe-free system,
then π is subject to a further constraint π ≤ 1/p1, which may bind and further reduce the
possibility of corruption. I will omit this possibility to save space and taxonomy.
**** Figure 7 about here ****
Let us consider some comparative statics of the partial reduction outcome as various
aspects of the formal and the community institutions improve.
Any improvement in the formal institution—an increase in the detection probabilities g
and h or the fine F – flatten the IEP contours. To see this, use the implicit function theorem
to derive the slope of a typical IEP contour
− [ h (π − 1) + g β ] F + { 1 − [ h (π − 1) + g β ] } β L = c .
This yields
∂π
∂β =
L − Lh(π − 1) − g (F + 2βL)
h (F + βL)
. (11)
It is easy to see that an increase in F or g reduces this. The effect of h is a bit more
complicated. Writing
∂π
∂β =
L − g (F + 2βL)
h (F + βL)

L (π − 1)
F + βL ,
we have

∂h "
∂π
∂β #
= −
L − g (F + 2βL)
h
2
(F + βL)
.
When ∂π/∂β > 0 as is the case in the relevant part of the space,
L − g (F + 2βL) > Lh(π − 1) > 0,
so

∂h "
∂π
∂β #
< 0 . In Figure 7, what happens as the formal enforcement improves is that the IEP contours become flatter, and the point of tangency C moves to the south-west along the feasible frontier, resulting in lower β and π, i.e. reduced corruption. Next consider improvements in the business community institution, i.e. an increase in the probability q of being convicted when guilty, and/or a decrease in the probability r of being wrongly convicted. When m increases and/or k decreases, the feasible frontier defined 16 by equality in (10) obviously shifts up, but we need to know what happens to its slope. Along it, we have ∂π ∂β = m (k − β) 2 = π 2 m . Therefore the shifted frontier becomes steeper as we move vertically up by increasing m or decreasing k at given β, but flatter as we move horizontally to the left by increasing m, and keeps the same slope when k decreases, at given π. The slope of IEP curves changes the opposite way. We see from (11) that moving vertically up at given β makes IEP curves flatter, and moving horizontally to the left at given β makes them steeper. Therefore, as the feasible frontier shifts up, in Figure 7 the tangency outcome must move somewhere between vertically upward and horizontally leftward to a point like C to the north-west, with lower β but higher π. (The figure shows such a comparison of C and the outcome B with no (or totally ineffective) business institution that was derived in Figure 3 and is now shown as the tangency of the two dashed curves.) Improvement of the business community institution reduces the magnitude of bribes the bureaucrats demand, but the chances of winning the license through bribery improve. Intuitively, as the business community increases its own expected penalties for winning a contract through bribery, the bureaucracy has to make it more attractive for businesspeople to comply with their demands, and they do this by combining smaller bribes and greater probability of success through bribery. Thus a small improvement in the business community institution has a mixed outcome. However, when the improvement progresses far enough, eventually the feasible set becomes empty and corruption is eliminated. 3 Practical Considerations Outside the Model The formal model of the previous section was highly simplified in a reduced form. Moreover, it studied only the equilibrium of the suggested institution, i.e. how it would maintain itself once it got going. Therefore the formal analysis must be supplemented by some informal discussion of practical matters of implementation. Here is a brief statement; for a more detailed discussion see Dixit (2013). 17 3.1 Requirements

The work of Ostrom (1990, 2007) and others has clarified some conditions that are necessary
for successful operation of self-sustaining communal institutions of collective action. In our
context, the following seem the most important ones.
3.1.1 Boundaries
The set of members, and their rights and duties, should be clearly defined. Here the business
association imposing the sanctions may have a set of members who have publicly declared
themselves to be bound by the norm. That will be valuable in ways mentioned later. These
members should also declare themselves to be bound by the sanctioning procedure, agreeing
to ostracize any firm that the association finds guilty of bribery, whether or not the guilty
firm has itself joined the association. That is, firms should not think themselves immune
from sanctions if they stay outside the group that has signed the no-bribery pledge.

3.1.2 Detection and adjudication

Monitoring and sanctioning is best done by members of the association through their delegated
representatives, using their local and insider knowledge, expertise and experience.
They can admit and interpret evidence on using broader criteria than can a general court.
As in Bernstein (1992) and Greif (1993), this will be conducive to a faster, less costly, and
more accurate process. Klitgaard (2012) discusses the comparative advantage of the business
community and the role of public-private partnerships for detecting and exposing corruption.
The business association can also pursue more pro-active strategies, for example sending its
agent-provocateurs to entrap corrupt officials and exposing them. However, in the context
of corruption, internal adjudication carries the danger that the association becomes an insiders’
clique, using the sanctioning power illegitimately to exclude newcomers and to preserve
an oligopoly of incumbents. This is indeed a serious risk, because cooperation in the anticorruption
institution can facilitate collusion or cartelization in the business community. To
maintain the integrity of the mechanism, it is crucial not only that the procedure is untainted,
but that it is seen to be untainted. For this, the adjudication tribunal should have
some representation of respected outsiders and of new firms, and its process should have
sufficient transparency to allay suspicion. Integrity and objectivity of the tribunal is also
important to reduce the risk that a firm is sanctioned because of false accusations by rival
firms.

18
3.1.3 Graduated sanctions

In most game-theoretic models of repeated prisoners’ dilemmas, good behavior is best sustained
by the harshest self-enforcing punishment. In practice, however, punishments that
are small for a first offense and only gradually become harsh are found to work best. This
seems equally valid in the context of corruption, especially because it reduces the risk of
wrongful conviction leading to permanent ouster from business. It may also help prevent the
morphing of the anti-corruption institution into one that deters new and innovative entry; if
a novice firm gains a foothold through bribery, it would not be immediately booted out but
be given a warning or a slap-on-the-wrist punishment like a small fine, and given a second
chance to stand on its own merit.
As sanctions are ratcheted up against persistent offenders, the business association may
strengthen then further by inviting consumers to join the ostracism or boycott against the
guilty firm.

3.1.4 Official recognition

We saw that the business institution has to work together with the government’s own anticorruption
efforts, although it does greatly increase the effectiveness of the latter. Conversely,
the government’s legal system should accept the business association’s verdicts, much as
courts show forbearance for verdicts of recognized private arbitration systems, standing
ready to enforce their verdicts and not hearing the cases again. The government can do
more. Many private firms and government departments that regularly award contracts have
lists of approved bidders. A preliminary scrutiny is carried out to put a firm on this list, and
in the competition for any specific contract only bids from firms on this list are considered.
The government can make it a requirement for being on the approved vendors’ list that the
firm is not ostracized for previous bribery by the business association. Of course, if such
a rule is adopted, that makes it all the more important that the association’s procedure
minimizes the risk of false conviction, and does not become a means of deterring entry to
preserve the insiders’ oligopoly.

3.2 Launching the Institution

Shifting an equilibrium is always difficult, and unfortunately, shifting from a good equilibrium
to a bad one is easier than shifting from a bad one to a good one. A rumor or some local
difficulty can start a bank run; creating or restoring confidence in the banking system is much
harder. Similarly, launching an anti-corruption institution is a difficult task, requiring much
effort in reputation-building and creating confidence that the system is going to function
sufficiently well. Here are just a few thoughts in this matter; more are sure to occur to
others as thinking and experimenting along these lines progresses further.

3.2.1 Selecting launch members

If the new institution is to get sufficiently rapid recognition and respect, it is essential that
several of the most respected leaders of the business community publicly declare their active
support and participation by becoming launching members and urging others to join. In
countries like India and China, these are most likely to come from the modern sectors of
the economy—information and communication technology, web-based businesses, consulting
etc.—who also do business in other countries with higher standards of governance and have
some incentive to maintain similar reputation and standards in their own countries. See
Khanna and Palepu (2004) for further discussion of such interactions. Once a sufficient mass
of respected members exists, others who stay out can be named and shamed into joining;
the media can be very helpful here. The government can also help recruitment by requiring
that a firm be a member in good standing of the business association as a condition for it to
be on the government’s list of approved vendors or bidders for government supply contracts
and licenses.

3.2.2 Earning and maintaining reputation

The worst thing that can happen to an anti-corruption organization is being tainted by a
scandal. The association in its early phases will have to be especially vigilant in its detection
and sanctioning, ready to expel and ostracize any members, no matter how important, who
are found in violation of the no-bribery norm. It will also have to be especially careful to
avoid any suspicion of being seen as a clique of big firms or insiders. To avoid the risk,
the community will have to make special efforts to recruit new, small, and innovative firms,
not only as members but as active members with representation on the adjudication and
decision-making bodies of the association. It should also get some outside experts and
respected citizens from outside business to serve as consultants or observers on these bodies.
20

3.2.3 Overcoming opposition

Businesses with relational capital invested in existing system will resist the new institution;
this resistance can take many forms and needs to be countered by all available means, including
the use of allies in the press and other media to name and shame the firms that
refuse to take the pledge. Resistance will also come from within the government, as many of
its politicians and officials stand to lose lucrative bribe incomes. Media campaigns can help;
proactive strategies to maintain good relations with the media will help deflect false accusations
of improprieties and attempts to create scandals to discredit the institution. More
generally, a recent comparative case study (Innovations for Successful Societies, 2014) of how
various governments’ anti-corruption agencies fared in building and maintaining reputations
can be useful here.

4 Concluding Comments

Corruption is endemic and entrenched in many countries. The community institution operating
on the supply side of bribery that I have proposed here cannot by itself eliminate
or even greatly reduce it. But it can significantly strengthen the effectiveness of the government’s
formal system of detection and punishment that operates mostly on the demand
side.
The analysis applies only to relationships between business firms and officials for awards
of government licenses and contracts. But the hope is that if such an institution becomes
established, that will help change the general culture of corruption in the country, and
thereby also help reduce corruption in other contexts such as extortion by officials and the
police in their dealings with individual citizens.
Therefore I hope the idea will be further scrutinized in research and attempted in some
country whose business community is sufficiently well organized and sufficiently adventurous
to experiment with novel ideas that have the potential to free it from the yoke of extortionate
demands of politicians and officials.


21
References


Aidt, Toke S. 2003. “Economic analysis of corruption: A survey.” Economic Journal 113,
November, F632–F652.
Ayyagari, Meghana, Aslı Demirg¨u¸c-Kunt and Vojislav Maksimovic. 2014. “Are Innovating
Firms Victims? Bribe Payments as a Tax on Innovation in Developing Countries.”
Working paper, Washington, DC: The World Bank.
Basu, Karna, Kaushik Basu, Tito Cordella and Aristomene Varoudakis. 2014. “Asymmetric
punishment as an instrument of corporate control.” Working Paper, Washington, DC:
The World Bank.
Basu, Kaushik. 2011. “Why, for a class of bribes, the act of giving a bribe should be treated
as legal.” Working paper, Ministry of Finance, Government of India. Available at
http://www.kaushikbasu.org/Act Giving Bribe Legal.pdf
Becker, Gary S. 1968. “Crime and punishment: An economics approach.” Journal of Political
Economy vol. 76, no. 2, March-April, pp. 169–217.
——— and George J. Stigler. 1974. “Law enforcement, malfeasance, and the compensation
of enforcers.” Journal of Legal Studies 3(1), January, 1–18.
Bernstein, Lisa. 1992. “Opting out of the legal system: Extralegal contractual relations in
the diamond industry.” Journal of Legal Studies 21(1), 115–157.
Dixit, Avinash. 2006. “Comparative statics for oligopoly.” International Economic Review
27(1), February, 107–122.
——— . 2013. “Corruption: Supply-side and demand-side solutions.” Text of Silver Jubilee
Lecture at the Indira Gandhi Institute for Development Research, Mumbai, India. To
be published in Mahendra S. Dev et al. (eds.), Development in India: Micro and Macro
Perspectives, Springer. Available at
https://www.princeton.edu/fdixitak/home/IGIDR 01.pdf
Greif, Avner. 1993. “Contract enforceability and economic institutions in early trade: The
Maghribi traders’ coalition.” American Economic Review 83(3), June, 525–548.
Innovations for Successful Societies. 2014. “From underdogs to watchdogs: How anticorruption
agencies can hold off potent adversaries.” Princeton University. Available
at https://www.princeton.edu/successfulsocieties
22
Khanna, Tarun and Krishna G. Palepu. 2004. “Globalization and convergence in corporate
governance: Evidence from Infosys and the Indian software industry.” Journal of
International Business Studies 35(6), November, 484–507.
Kingston, Christopher. 2008. “Social Structure and Cultures of Corruption.” Journal of
Economic Behavior and Organization 67(1): 90–102.
Klitgaard, Robert. 2012. “Public-Private collaboration and corruption.” In Mark Pieth (ed.)
Collective Action: Innovative Strategies to Prevent Corruption, Zurich/St. Gallen: Dike
Verlag AG, 41–66.
Ostrom, Elinor. 1990. Governing the Commons. New York, NY and Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
——— . 2007. “Collective action theory.” In Carles Boix and Susan Stokes (eds) Oxford
Handbook of Comparative Politics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 186–208.
Rose-Ackerman, Susan. Corruption: A Study in Political Economy. New York: Academic
Press.
——— . 2010. “The law and economics of bribery and corruption.” Annual Review of Law
and Social Science 6, 217–238.
Seade, Jes´us K. 2003. “Prices, profits and taxes in oligopoly.” University of Warwick, UK:
Research Paper in Economics No. 260.
Strouse, Jean. 2000. Morgan: American Financier. New York: HarperCollins.
Superti, Chiara. 2009. “Addiopizzo: Can a label defeat the Mafia?” Journal of International
Policy Solutions 11, Spring, 3–11.
23
1
/
`
EP0
1
Figure 1: Bureaucrat’s Payoff Contours
24
1
/
`
1
/=1/(1<`) Figure 2: Willingness to Pay Bribe without Institution 25 1 / ` EP0 1 U B EP* /=1/(1<`) . Figure 3: Outcome without Institution 26 1 / ` 1 /=m/(k<`) /=1/(1<`) k m/k Figure 4: Willingness to Pay Bribe with Institution 27 1 π β EP0 1 U B EP* π=1/(1−β) . π=m/(k−β) m/k k Figure 5: Corruption-free Outcome with Institution – 1 28 1 / ` EP0 1 /=1/(1<`) /=m/(k<`) m/k k / = 1/p1 Figure 6: Corruption-free Outcome with Institution – 2 29 1 / ` EP0 1 /=1/(1<`) /=m/(k<`) m/k k . EP’ . EP* B C Figure 7: Partial Reduction in Corruption Source:http://www.princeton.edu/~dixitak/home/ABCDE_Dixit_3.pdf

ChatGPT, una introducción realista, por Ariel Torres

The following information is used for educational purposes only.           ChatGPT, una introducción realista    ChatGPT parece haber alcanz...